Explaining Religious Terrorism Part 2:
Politics, Religion, and the Suspension of the Ethical
August 23, 2004, Author(s): Mark Burgess
In recent years, a tendency towards increasing
violence manifested itself across terrorism generally, with twice as many
fatalities caused by terrorist attacks between 1980 and 1986 than had been the
case in the preceding seven-year period.1 Religious terrorism proved especially prone
to these higher levels of violence. By
1993, this was particularly evident from the record of Shia
Islamic terrorist groups. Such groups
inflicted 30 percent of the fatalities from terrorist acts since 1982, yet
carried out just eight percent of all international terrorist attacks during
the same period. As discussed in part one of
this article in CDI’s Explaining
Terrorism series, this appetite
for extreme violence was not restricted to Muslim groups, but shared by
terrorists from across the religious spectrum.2
Various
reasons have been suggested to account for the religious terrorist’s wiliness,
if not eagerness, to indulge in mass-casualty attacks.3
For instance, a degree of ‘systematic desensitization’ may have taken
place among both terrorists and their targets and audiences, with increasing
casualty tolls seen as necessary if the acts of terrorism are to achieve their
goals. However, while such a phenomenon
may indeed have taken place to some extent, this does not easily equate with
the trend towards casualty aversion that has also been observed in high-income,
low-birthrate societies - something that might just as easily allow (perhaps even
assist) terrorists to achieve their aims by inflicting lower rather than higher casualty rates.
Likewise,
while the improved technological means available today has undoubtedly enhanced
their capacity to inflict death and injury on a large scale, this does not, in
itself, account for the religious terrorist’s tendency towards (and success
with) such attacks. As has been noted
elsewhere, religious terrorists dating back as far as two millennia have
achieved sustained casualty rates and affected their respective societies to a
degree yet to be attained by their modern-day counterparts.4
All these factors point to the religious terrorist’s desired ends being
the key factor in raising the threshold of death and destruction that they are
capable of - something accentuated, but not primarily driven, by their
available means or these means’ perceived effect.
Identifying Religious Terrorism
Of all religious
terrorists, the Thugs - a Hindu sect active in India from the seventh until
the mid-19th centuries - are probably the only historical example to be moved
purely by religious motives.5
As this suggests, a group does not need to be wholly motivated by
religious considerations to be considered religious terrorists. However, if the term is to retain a useful
meaning, religious terrorism should be considered that terrorism which is
motivated primarily by religion. An ethnic or (politically) ideological
terrorist group does not cease to be so because their proponents have a
religious element to their makeup - even if that religious element must be
considered if any study of the group is to be effective.
The
view that it is their motivation that sets the religious terrorist apart from
their secular equivalents is not held by all commentators. In his article “The Worldwide Rise of
Religious Nationalism,” one, Mark Jurgensmeyer,
breaks what he sees as the “potentially explosive mix of nationalism and
religion” into two subsets: Ethnic and Ideological.6
He differentiates these two categories thus, supplying examples of each
One of the
greatest differences between the goals of religious nationalists is the degree
to which religion is an aspect of ethnic identity - the sort of religious
nationalism one finds in Ireland, for
example - and the degree to which it is part of an ideological critique that
contains an alternative vision of political order. The latter is the sort
of religious nationalism found, for instance, in the Ayatollah Khomeini's
Islamic Revolution in Iran.7
Such
a reading, while addressing the religious element that is often present in many
secular terrorist groups and the degree to which this is a factor, arguably
risks misrepresenting such group’s aspirations and motivations, and, as a
result, mislabeling them in calling them religious terrorists. To take the case of the Northern Ireland
conflict that is expounded upon by Jurgensmeyer as an
example of “Ethnic Religious Nationalism” - in this and subsequent work8 - the protagonists are indeed
divided along religious lines, with Republicans (who seek to abolish the
Northern Irish state and unify the north and south of Ireland) invariably
Catholic, and Loyalists (who seeks to maintain Northern Ireland as part of the
United Kingdom) Protestant. Both sides
also often express their hatred for each other in religiously-loaded rhetoric,
and frequently resort to religious imagery and symbolism in promoting their
respective political agendas. However,
such groups are overwhelmingly motivated by a political not a religious
imperative. As such, they should be
considered secular rather than religious terrorists.
The
same can be said of the Jewish organizations which were active before Israel
became a state, and even of many of the various (nominally Muslim)
organizations such as those operated under the auspices of the Palestinian
Liberation Organization. Like the
Northern Irish examples, the religious aspect of such groups is mainly a
reflection of their membership demographic rather than their motivations. Religion is important, but not the main
motivation for such groups. This
differentiates them from others, for whom the religious imperative is foremost,
and who can correctly be considered religious terrorists. This distinction is far from mere
semantics. As with a medical
misdiagnosis, a failure to correctly recognize the motivations of specific
terrorist groups makes arriving at adequate countermeasures immeasurably more
difficult if not impossible.
Degrees of Religious Terrorism
At the danger of making
the issue appear deceptively simple, Figure 1 attempts to break the dynamics
that differentiate religious and secular activity - including terrorism - down
to their bare components. Of the two
axes shown here, the means continuum is the easier to supervise - although, as
the ongoing (albeit lower level) violence by Loyalist and Republican groups
(despite most such groups ostensibly observing ceasefires) there shows, this is
far from a clear-cut demarcation. To
paraphrase the 17th Century Dutch philosopher Benedict de Spinoza, peace
is not merely the absence of war.
By comparison, the
crossing of the secular-religious line is much more difficult to monitor. This is further complicated as groups do not
necessarily remain at a static point within the quadrants formed by the
ends-means axes. A group may increase or
decrease the religiosity of its ends or the violence of its means. For instance, it has been claimed of the
Islamic Movement of Uzbekistan that it shifted its mission from fighting
injustice domestically to inciting Islamic extremism globally, with its
invocation of a global jihad earning it financial support from Iran, Pakistan, Saudi Arabia and Turkey.9
Similarly, there is evidence of disillusionment among Kashmiri militants
at what is seen as the transformation of a religious struggle into one that is
being waged in the interests of the state of Pakistan.10
Often such realignment
of ends or means (or both) will be almost imperceptible. For example, al Qaeda’s
offer of a truce to European nations in the wake of Spain’s announcement that it
was withdrawing its troops from Iraq, while far from
political dialogue in its true sense, does indicates that Osama
bin Laden’s organization may not be as opposed to
negotiation or discourse as was previously thought. Moreover, while al Qaeda’s
enemies may not currently be disposed to negotiate with the group, this may not
always be the case - witness for example the Reagan administration’s dealings
with Iranian state terrorists or Margaret Thatcher’s with the Provisional Irish
Republican Army. Furthermore, as the
British experience with the latter group illustrates, nudging a group across
the violent (terrorism)/non-violent (political dialogue) line can be an
integral and vital component of a counter-terrorism strategy.
In addition, groups will
often straddle the various quadrants. Al
Qaeda again supplies a good illustration of
this. The group undertook reconstruction
projects in Sudan and Afghanistan even as it planned and
carried out attacks. Bin Laden’s group also has a distinct political tint to it
religious ambitions - in this case the ultimate aim being the establishment of
a pan-Islamic state - meaning that it bestrides all four quadrants to varying
degrees. This political aspect is
present with all religious terrorist groups, but particularly salient with
regard to Muslims. Historically, the
Islamic faith has not embraced the separation of church and state to the degree
that is common in Western countries - most especially the United States. 11
This blurring of
religion-and-politics/politics-and-religion that is characteristic of religious
terrorism expresses itself in two forms.
The first of these - the politicization of religion - attempts to apply
political solutions (in the form of political violence through terrorism) to
religious problems. It is religious terrorism that is more religious than
political, although, as stated previously, this can change with the political
imperative becoming the more dominant. Religious
terrorism’s second form of expression - the religionization
of politics - attempts to apply religious solutions to political problems
(again in the form of terrorism). Such
attempts involve efforts to justify the violence, and attract and motivate
terrorists, through religious rhetoric. It
is religious terrorism that is more political than religious. This can also change with the religious
imperative becoming the more dominant.
The mixing of religion
and politics can be an oddly ecumenical and non-sectarian phenomenon: according
to one of Israel’s former chiefs, the
political and religious nature of their goals means that Jewish radical-right
groups have much in common with Hamas.12
How this mix is adjusted leads to degrees of religious terrorism - from
terrorism motivated (and a priori justified by) by religion, to terrorism
justified by religion and merely masquerading as religious terrorism. Both versions can be similarly difficult to
counter. Indeed, it is easy to imagine a
scenario whereby religion, hitherto used by the leaders of a terrorist campaign
(as in the latter variant) as a means of attracting and indoctrinating recruits
as well as attracting and sustaining support, can become the chief driving
factor. In short, the religious
imperative can be as difficult to limit and control as it is to counter.
Rationalizing
Religious Terrorism
Underlying this is the
fact that, while it is their ends which set the religious terrorists apart from
their secular counterparts, their means are also noteworthy and tend to be less
restricted, resulting in higher levels of - often more indiscriminate -
killing. This is not to say, as one
scholar does, that religious terrorists are their own constituency, and
“execute their terrorist acts for no audience by themselves.”13
This might be true were it not for the political considerations also
inherent in the thinking of even those terrorists motivated primarily by
religion. Al Qaeda
may have wanted to kill a lot of people in attacking America on Sept. 11, 2001, not to say exact revenge for the wrongs they
considered the United States to have inflicted on
the Muslim world; however they also wanted to stage a publicity coup for
themselves in telegraphing to the world what they were capable of. Similarly, the Taliban illustrated their
appreciation of the need for political expediency to outweigh religious zeal
when, in January 2004, they publicly
apologized after one of their bomb attacks left 15 people - eight of them
children - dead in Khandahar, Afghanistan.
As such incidents show,
the terror inflicted by the religious terrorist is not an end in itself.14
Rather is a means towards a larger goal.
Nor is this goal a conventional one.
As the U.S. National Commission on
Terrorism put it: “Today’s terrorists don’t want a seat at the table, they want
to destroy the table and everyone sitting at it.”15
In addition, those whose terrorism has a religious nature or motivation
see themselves as answerable only to God (or their idea of God) and their
activities as divinely sanctioned. As a
consequence, they operate within different moral, political, and practical
constraints than secular terrorists. Far
from being their own audience, the religious terrorist’s ultimate constituency
is God.
The
paradox of such violence being undertaken in the name of anyone’s idea of a
good and just God, as religious terrorism tends to be (generally speaking
religious terrorists no more consider themselves evil than do their secular
counterparts - indeed they consider themselves righteous) was perhaps best
addressed by the 19th century Danish
philosopher Søren Kierkegaard. Writing
pseudonymously as Johannes de Silentio, in Fear and Trembling, Kierkegaard
considered the dilemma of whether there can exist a “teleological suspension of
the ethical” - a situation wherein normal moral considerations are justifiably
over-ridden when appealing to a higher ideal.16
Examining the case of Abraham - a pivotal figure in Christianity, Islam,
and Judaism, who was prepared to sacrifice his own son when ordered to do so
(as a test of his faith) by God - Kierkegaard concludes (some might say
somewhat equivocally) that such a suspension can indeed exist. It seems likely that this conclusion (which
Kierkegaard views as a temporary expedient and not an abolishment of ‘normal’
ethical considerations) is shared by religious terrorists - or at least those
who terrorism is genuinely motivated by their religious convictions (however
misguided), as distinct from those who seek to justify their use of violence or
recruit others to their cause by the subjective interpretation of religious
doctrine.
As this implies, the religious
terrorist cannot, as is sometimes suggested, be dismissed as an irrational
madman anymore than his secular counterpart can. Just as terrorism often resides in the eye of
the beholder, so too does rationality. To
the religious terrorist, their actions are imminently rational, predicated as
they are (or are taken by them to be) on the will of God. Dismissing a terrorist group as irrational on
the grounds that its rationality differs from their own is something that the United States and the West can
ill-afford to do if they also hope to defuse the threat posed by religious
terrorism. Likewise, insisting that
religious terrorists such as al Qaeda are fighting
the United States because of a hatred of
liberty, freedom, or the American way of life is of no use in countering
them. Indeed, it may even prove
counterproductive. Understanding one’s
enemy is a prerequisite to defeating them on the conventional battlefield. It is an even more crucial consideration on
the unconventional one - especially when, as now, the enemy being faced is a
religious terrorist.
Notes
1 Bruce
Hoffman, "The Contrasting Ethical Foundations of Terrorism in the
1980s," Terrorism & Political
Violence 1, no. 3 (1989), p. 361, n. 1. This cites statistics from the Rand
Corporation’s Chronology of International Terrorism. According to this 1573 people were killed by
terrorists during 1973-1979, whereas 3,225 people were killed by the same means
between 1980 and 1986.
2 Bruce
Hoffman, “`Holy Terror’: The Implications of Terrorism Motivated by a Religious
Imperative," Studies in Conflict
& Terrorism 18, no. 4 (1995). The
figure on casualties versus attacks by Islamic terrorist groups is again taken
from the Rand chronology.
3 See, for instance, Wilkinson, Paul. Conflict Study 236: "Terrorist
Targets and Tactics: New Risks to World Order." (Washington: Research
Institute for the Study of Conflict and Terrorism, 1990), which considers this
question.
4 David
C. Rapoport, "Fear and Trembling: Terrorism in
Three Religious Traditions,"
American Political Science Review 78, no. 3 (1984), p. 659.
5 See, Ibid. for more on the Thugs. Also, Mark Burgess, "A Brief History
of Terrorism," Center for Defense Information (2003),
and Mark Burgess, "Explaining
Religious Terrorism Part 1: The Axis of Good and Evil," Center for Defense Information (2004).
6 Mark Juergensmeyer, " The Worldwide Rise of Religious
Nationalism," Journal of
International Affairs 50, no. 1 (1996), p. 2.
7 Ibid.,
p. 4.
8 See also, Mark Juergensmeyer,
"Terror Mandated by God,"
Terrorism & Political Violence 9, no. 2 (1997), or Mark Juergensmeyer, Terror
In The Mind Of God : The Global Rise of Religious Violence, 3rd , rev. and
updated. (Berkeley: University of California Press, 2003).
9 Jessica
Stern, Terror in The Name of God : Why
Religious Militants Kill, 1st ed. (New York: Ecco,
2003), p. 267.
10 Ibid., pp. 134-137.
11 For more on this topic see, John L. Esposito, Islam and Politics, 4th ed. (Syracuse,
N.Y.: Syracuse University Press, 1998).
12 Stern,
Op Cit., p. 106.
13
Hoffman, “’Holy Terror’: The Implications of Terrorism Motivated by a
Religious Imperative," p. 273.
14 Such a notion is put forward in S. K. Malik, The Quranic Concept of War, 1st ed. (Lahore: Wajidalis, 1979).
Cited in Yossef Bodansky,
Bin Laden : The Man Who Declared War on
America, (Rocklin, Calif.: Forum, 1999), p. xv.
15
National Commission on Terrorism, "Countering the Changing Threat of International Terrorism: Report of
the National Commission on Terrorism," (2000), p. 2.
16 Sören Kierkegaard, Fear
and Trembling, (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1941) The entire
text is available on-line at: http://www.religion-online.org/showbook.asp?title=2068 . Last downloaded April 22, 2004.
|